ABSTRACT
The concerted responses of eusocial insects to environmental stimuli are often referred to as collective cognition at the level of the colony. To achieve collective cognition, a group can draw on two different sources: individual cognition and the connectivity between individuals. Computation in neural networks, for example, is attributed more to sophisticated communication schemes than to the complexity of individual neurons. The case of social insects, however, can be expected to differ. This is because individual insects are cognitively capable units that are often able to process information that is directly relevant at the level of the colony. Furthermore, involved communication patterns seem difficult to implement in a group of insects as they lack a clear network structure. This review discusses links between the cognition of an individual insect and that of the colony. We provide examples for collective cognition whose sources span the full spectrum between amplification of individual insect cognition and emergent group-level processes.
Introduction
The individuals that make up a social insect colony are so tightly knit that they are often regarded as a single super-organism (Wilson and Hölldobler, 2009). This point of view seems to go far beyond a simple metaphor (Gillooly et al., 2010) and encompasses aspects of the colony that are analogous to cell differentiation (Emerson, 1939), metabolic rates (Hou et al., 2010; Waters et al., 2010), nutrient regulation (Behmer, 2009), thermoregulation (Jones, 2004; Starks et al., 2000), gas exchange (King et al., 2015) and more.
It is tempting to push this analogy one step further and attribute the superorganism with collective cognition (Couzin, 2009; Franks, 1989; Seeley, 1995). In this respect, it is possible to envision two extreme cases in which groups of insects may have evolved to exhibit cognition on the scale of the entire colony. The first is reliance on the cognition of the individuals that make up the group. Indeed, the cognitive abilities of a single ant or bee within the large colony are far from being simple (Dornhaus and Franks, 2008). The group can benefit from these capabilities, for example, by sharing and refining the knowledge of informed individuals. The second extreme case is collective cognition derived from the interaction between members. Man-made systems teach us that complex computation can be achieved by the wiring together of very simple components such as logical gates (Lindgren and Nordahl, 1990). Similarly, social insect colonies often display dense interaction networks (Wilson and Hölldobler, 1988) and collective behaviors that appear to exceed the capacity of the individuals of which they are constituted (Sumpter, 2006).
It is therefore of interest to trace the collective actions of the social insect colony to their sources, be they the cognition of individuals or the communication network that connects groups of such individuals. Mapping out the relations between these two organizational scales is required if we are to understand and quantify collective cognition as well as learn about its evolutionary origins. We hypothesize that individual-based collective behaviors will be prevalent in cases where abilities, similar to those exhibited by solitary insects, suffice in order to sense, grasp and process knowledge that is relevant on the scale of the colony. Deviations from this will tend to lead to group solutions that involve an increased emergent component.
First, we discuss the cognitive abilities of the individuals that make up the social insect colony as well as some of the current knowledge of communication networks in social insects. As mentioned above, these two components provide the basis on which the colony could build its collective capabilities. Next, we present a list of examples of collective cognition. These examples are ordered by the degree to which collective behaviors rely on each of the two components, from individual based to connectivity based. The examples are split into three categories: (1) individual-based collective behaviors, (2) collective behaviors that combine different individual perspectives, and (3) collective behaviors that display higher levels of emergence. Each of these categories is divided into subcategories that further refine this division. Taken together, these examples span a broad spectrum of relationships between individual and collective cognition. In the final section, we discuss possible factors that may determine the degree of emergence in a particular collective behavior.
Individual cognition
A good starting point for discussing the origins of cognition in social insect colonies is the cognitive abilities of solitary insects. Insect brains evolved hundreds of millions of years (Farris and Schulmeister, 2011; Ma et al., 2012) prior to the appearance of eusociality (Moreau, 2006). Despite the fact that their brains are relatively small (Chittka and Niven, 2009), solitary insects exhibit high cognitive skills that include large behavioral repertoires (Evans, 1966) and complex forms of learning (Alloway, 1972; Blackiston et al., 2011), and their navigational skills often exceed those of humans (Brower, 1996). These abilities aid the solitary insect in foraging (O'Neill, 2001), finding or constructing shelters (Raw, 1972), confronting predators (Schmidt, 1990) and identifying appropriate mating partners (Dickson, 2008).
The next step in this discussion is the transition to eusociality, which happened between 100 and 150 million years ago (Brady et al., 2006; Engel et al., 2009). Eusociality is characterized by reproductive division of labor that drastically lowers the level of conflict between group members as they strive towards common goals (Crespi and Yanega, 1995). First, it is important to state that, unlike cells in a tissue or neurons in the brain, insects within the colony superorganism maintain their individuality. They are capable of autonomous motion and decision making. Furthermore, the brains of individuals within a colony bear high resemblance to those of solitary insects (Strausfeld, 1976). One may therefore ask how the cognitive capabilities of a social insect compare with those of a solitary insect. To date, it is not clear if evolution works on large groups to increase or decrease the cognitive complexity of individuals. On the one hand, it is known, mainly from vertebrate groups that the communication requirements of group living may work to increase brain complexity (Shultz and Dunbar, 2010). On the other hand, it has been suggested that relying on collective processes may ease the energetically expensive maintenance of brain tissue (Aiello and Wheeler, 1995; Anderson and McShea, 2001; Feinerman and Traniello, 2016).
Whatever the exact comparison between the brains of a social and a solitary insect, it is clear that the social insect is a cognitively capable individual. Individuals within the colony possess the capacity for large behavioral repertoires (Chittka and Niven, 2009), for weighing a large number of factors to reach individual decisions (Franks et al., 2003) and for navigating over large distances (Gathmann and Tscharntke, 2002; Wehner, 2003). Importantly, these individual capabilities are relevant on the scale of the entire colony.
One aspect that clearly differentiates the social insect from its solitary counterpart is the capacity for communication. For example, eusocial insects display a huge diversification of cuticular pheromones (van Wilgenburg et al., 2011) used to convey multiple signals that are unique to colony life (Howard and Blomquist, 2005). Another famous example is the honeybee waggle dance (Von Frisc, 1950). While solitary insects may have the motivation to conceal a newly found item for personal consumption (Byrne et al., 2003), bees have evolved an elaborate communication scheme which allows them to share this location. These and other interaction skills form the foundation of insect society. In the next section, we discuss some of the properties of the communication networks via which social insects coordinate their activities.
Interaction networks
Animals living in groups combine personal and social information when deciding upon their next action (Rieucau and Giraldeau, 2011). In eusocial insects, the social component of information collection is especially important (Wilson and Hölldobler, 1988). Correspondingly, the modalities of communication and richness of cues and signals is greatly enhanced. Social insects use a variety of olfactory (Martin and Drijfhout, 2009; Morgan, 2009), tactile (Razin et al., 2013), visual and vibrational (Delattre et al., 2015; Roces et al., 1993) messages, as well as multi-modal combinations of these (Jaffé et al., 1990) in their communication. Broadly speaking, these can be divided into several groups: some messages require direct contact between individuals and can thus be considered as local in both space and time. Other signals are local in time but not space and are typically employed as alarm signals (e.g. highly volatile pheromones; Blum, 1969). Yet another group are signals that are local in space but not in time. This group includes stigmergic, indirect communication between insects in which one individual modifies the environment and a second individual arriving at the same location at some later time reacts to its modified surroundings (Theraulaz and Bonabeau, 1999). Mass recruitment pheromone trails (Jaffe and Howse, 1979) and nest construction without a blueprint (Franks and Deneubourg, 1997) are two impressive examples of stigmergy. Note that, for the case of pheromonal communication, the time scales that characterize pheromonal communication are evolvable as they depend on chemical evaporation times that, do indeed, vary between species and tasks (Morgan, 2009; Witte et al., 2007; Holldobler and Wilson, 1990).
Quantifying the communication patterns requires descriptive frameworks for the different interaction types as described above. Contact-dependent interactions can be described as time-ordered communication networks (Blonder and Dornhaus, 2011; Fewell, 2003; Moreau et al., 2011). It has been shown that, in a laboratory setting, the high mobility of social insects dictates that, after a sufficient time window, interactions occur between practically all possible pairs and the network becomes highly connected (Mersch et al., 2013). Stigmergic communication has been described by using the language of statistical mechanics (Richardson et al., 2011) or by employing cellular-automata tools typically used to describe self-organization processes (Khuong et al., 2016). These interactions are, inherently, one-to-many signaling and have been shown to extend the connectivity induced by contact-dependent communication (Richardson and Gorochowski, 2015). When also considering long-range communication, such as that involving alarm pheromones, we obtain a picture of a system in which, at least to first approximation and over long enough time scales, interactions can be described as well mixed. In other words, over time an insect receives signals from any other insect in the colony. Not only are interactions mixed, they are also, to a large extent anonymous. With a few exceptions (Mallon and Franks, 2000; Tibbetts, 2002), it is reasonable to assume that individuals do not recognize which of the hundreds to hundreds of thousands of other individuals they are currently interacting with.
While the previous discussion seems to suggest that interactions are completely ergodic, it is important to stress that the social insect colony is, by no means, devoid of structure. For example, ant nests and bee hives are often concentrically arranged such that young insects reside in the deep center while older individuals progressively occupy areas that are closer to the boundaries or entrance (Beshers and Fewell, 2001). Even when structure is initially lacking, self-organization and amplification of noise can work to create spatio-temporal patterns over time (Richardson et al., 2011; Theraulaz et al., 2003). Moreover, ant (Tschinkel, 2004) and termite (Noirot and Darlington, 2000) nests exhibit complex structures of rooms and corridors and these further reflect on the spatial distribution of individuals within the nest. It has been shown that different individuals tend to occupy specific locations or chambers within the nest (Jandt and Dornhaus, 2009; Sendova-Franks and Franks, 1995) and this reflects on the probability that they interact with other individuals in other parts of the nest (Mersch et al., 2013; Pinter-Wollman et al., 2011). Spatial locations therefore induce a network structure that is composed of relatively stable clusters. Hence, in a very broad sense, the communication patterns in a social insect colony can be viewed as residing between a well-mixed (on the more local scale) and a fixed (on the global, cluster scale) network.
Collective cognition
Having described some of the basic ‘cognitive toolbox’ available to the colony, we now discuss its collective scale behavioral products. We present a non-comprehensive list of examples for collective behaviors in social insect colonies. The examples were chosen while focusing on the different possible gaps between the knowledge, actions and capabilities of individuals compared with those of the entire group. They are ordered by the extent of this gap and divided between individual-based collective cognition (small gaps) and emergent collective cognition that builds on the interaction between insects (large gaps). This division is, by no means, strict.
Individual-based collective cognition
In a eusocial colony, the genetic conflict between individuals in the group is minimal (Queller and Strassmann, 1998). This leads to an alignment of interests, which implies that it is generally advantageous for informed individuals to share their knowledge with other group members. Utilizing this information is useful for the group as well. Since the number of informed individuals may be small, one could expect that their actions are too weak to elicit any significant effect or, alternatively, they may be averaged out against opposing actions performed by other, less-informed, colony members. Instead of losing this useful information, it may be profitable for the group to amplify the actions of these focal individuals. Any such amplification should be regulated to prevent runaway behavior in case of mistakes. Such mistakes could arise from the informed individuals themselves: they may hold only partial information or be plain wrong, or from communication: noisy interactions may distort the original message.
Next, we discuss several examples of amplification circuits that make the products of individual cognition available, effective and useful at the level of the group.
Unconditional amplification
The simplest example of unconditional amplification is the alarm response. When an individual ant senses danger, she not only directly reacts to it but further emits a volatile alarm pheromone (Blum, 1969). This pheromone spreads around the ant, eliciting similar responses from her neighboring nest-mates. This positive feedback circuit quickly spreads the danger signal to affect a large number of individuals (Jeanson and Deneubourg, 2009). This not only increases the group's surveillance of its environment (the ‘many eyes principle’), but also allows it to take collective actions towards, for example, protection of the nest. Similar behaviors are displayed by termites where chemical communication is accompanied by vibrational signaling (Delattre et al., 2015).
These collective positive feedback circuits provide an informed individual that senses danger with immediate and direct control over the actions of the group. In other words, the gap between individual and collective cognition is, practically, nonexistent. The group forsakes regulation and outweighs this crucial survival response over the possible price paid by false alarms.
Conditioned amplification
The mass recruitment foraging trail is a conditioned amplification that occurs when a single first ant locates a food source. This ant then uses her navigational skills to return to the nest while laying a pheromone trail that recruits others to the food such that foraging commences. While an emergent process may work to straighten the trail and make it shorter (see below) the trail still follows the qualitative solution as first discovered and then communicated by the initial recruiter (Holldobler, 1971).
Importantly, in a large number of species, ants strengthen the initial trail only on the way back from the target food source and only if they independently found it to be profitable (Beckers et al., 1992a; Mailleux et al., 2003; Wilson, 1962). This regulation can be considered as ‘delayed’ since it occurs only after an initial positive response to the initial ant. This provides a mechanism by which the group ‘double-checks’ the target communicated by the initial ant before continuing to amplify her effect even further. It allows the colony to reduce its response to ants that may have outdated information or are, for some reason, confused. Since pheromones are volatile and have a finite lifetime, their concentration along the trail depends on the rate at which they are enhanced. A trail that is not enhanced will eventually disappear. Thus, delayed regulation further supplies a mechanism for calibrating the level of activity on the recruitment trail (Simon and Hefetz, 1992), discontinuing it once the food source is exhausted (Wilson, 1962). It further allows the system to escape local minima by switching to foraging on more profitable food sources when such are identified (Beekman and Dussutour, 2009).
Amplification with early regulation
Desert ants typically forage alone and display only a rudimentary form of recruitment (Amor et al., 2010; Razin et al., 2013). The recruitment process occurs as ants that are informed about a food source outside the nest attempt to alert their nest-mates using imperfect communication. The interactions used are noisy in the sense that a recruitment interaction may be ignored or, conversely, a non-recruitment interaction may induce an ant to leave the nest. Therefore, amplification of the initial signal must be regulated so that recruitment occurs only when a food source is present and runaway behavior that results from mere interaction noise is avoided. It was shown that desert ants regulate recruitment early on in the process, at the entrance chamber of their nest (Razin et al., 2013).
This regulation is the result of two behavioral components. The first is the fact that individuals ‘know that they know’ (Greenwald et al., 2015). There is a clear difference in the way directly and non-directly informed insects react to interactions with others (Razin et al., 2013; Schultz et al., 2008; Stroeymeyt et al., 2011). For example, ants that have been to the food area simply disregard interactions and maintain high walking speed to increase the number and effectiveness of their recruitment interactions (Razin et al., 2013). However, ants with second-hand knowledge react to interactions in a more cautious manner. These ants can either upregulate or downregulate their propensity to be recruited depending on the state of the individual they interact with (Razin et al., 2013). These rules allow the ants to regulate collective behavior with minimal dependence on their unreliable communication skills. Specifically, this works to decrease the chances that the actions of non-informed ants have global consequences on the state of the nest and leaves the ‘stage’ to the directly informed ants (Razin et al., 2013).
The second regulatory component is an early negative feedback. All else being equal, non-informed ants tend to lower their propensity to exit with passing time. This leads to a collective threshold that dissipates the effects of random or isolated interactions such that their effect quickly dies away and this protects the system from noise. A persistent informed ant with first-hand information can generate enough activity such that interaction rates increase (Gordon and Mehdiabadi, 1999) and the system moves over this recruitment threshold. This early feedback mechanism in which positive feedback occurs only if the system passes a set threshold is similar to the generation of spikes in neurons (Razin et al., 2013). Note that while delayed regulation (as described above) works to regulate the amplitude of the collective response and terminate it when the stimulus ends, early regulation works to prevent amplification in the first place.
Combining individual perspectives
Amplifying the optimal option
The social insect colony may do more than amplifying individual decisions – it can, in fact, poll individuals to reach a consensus choice regarding the best solution among several alternative options. Examples for this come from house-hunting behaviors in ants (Visscher, 2007; Franks et al., 2002) and bees (Visscher et al., 2006). When assessing the quality of a potential new nest site, scout ants have been shown to incorporate an intricate, individually based, evaluation scheme that combines the different attributes of this location (e.g. its volume, the size of the door and the level of light) in a non-trivial way (Franks et al., 2003). There is evidence that this assessment results in a single grade given by the ant to the new location (Robinson et al., 2011, 2014). The group does not make its own assessments of nest quality [a hypothetical example for this could be moving the whole colony to occupy the alternative nests one at a time and using the resulting ant density (Gordon et al., 1993) to accurately measure the area of each], but rather uses quorum sensing as a polling mechanism to compare the assessments of its individual scouts (Franks et al., 2002; Visscher et al., 2006). This typically allows the colony to choose the best among the alternatives, with the accuracy of the decision growing with the size of the group (Sasaki et al., 2013).
House-hunting provides another fascinating example of how the action of the group may work to refine individual decisions: when comparing different nests with specific attributes, individual ants are prone to violate the regularity principle of rational decision-making (Sasaki and Pratt, 2011). This principle states that if option A is preferred over option B then this should not change upon introducing a third option, C, that is inferior to both. This fallacy is not specific to insects, but rather affects many different animals, including humans. However, when a whole colony is presented with the choice between these nests, it will tend to make the rational choice (Edwards and Pratt, 2009; Sasaki and Pratt, 2011). This is because the polling often terminates before individual ants have had the chance to fail the regularity principle since this requires visiting multiple nests (Robinson et al., 2014).
We provide several examples here (many more exist) of how the actions and decisions of capable individuals reflect at the level of the group. The group does not create new solutions but rather works to amplify, average, poll and refine the actions of individual members. This is done using collective communication circuits that involve positive and negative feedbacks and certain non-linearities.
Amplification in dynamic settings
In dynamic, fast-evolving scenarios, information can quickly become obsolete and the individuals that carry useful information change over time (Robson and Traniello, 2002; Gelblum et al., 2015). This entails two inherent problems: First, the relevant individual at a specific point in time has to be identified by the group. Second, when an individual that is better updated appears, the group must revert to following it instead.
This scenario is realized during cooperative transport by longhorn crazy ants (Czaczkes and Ratnieks, 2013). When ants cooperatively transport a large food item, they can often lose orientation and become unknowledgeable regarding the correct way to the nest. To correct their path, these ants rely on well-informed individuals that are in the vicinity of the load but unattached to it (Gelblum et al., 2015).
Instead of identifying the ant that currently holds valuable navigational information, here again, the group relies on the ‘know that you know’ principle. In other words, an informed ant acts in a manner that is different from the other carriers: she attaches to the object and, without heeding to others, pulls it in the direction she knows to be correct. At the same time the carrying ants ‘acknowledge that they don't know’ and apply a different behavioral rule – which is, in a sense, pull in the direction in which the load is currently moving. Together, these different rules as applied by informed and non-informed ants allow the group to optimally amplify the force of the informed leader (Gelblum et al., 2015).
Importantly, after a period of about 10 s, the newly attached leader loses her orientation. This former leader then adapts the behavioral rules of an ordinary carrier and may continue in this state for many minutes. The directionality of the carrying group is next corrected by the attachment of a new leader ant that happened to be informed at that particular time. The fast switching between leaders can be viewed as a mechanism that enables the group to escape being trapped at local minima in which the group displays coordinated motion but the direction is wrong.
Collective bootstrapping of individual solutions
Another form of colony-level solution that is based on the actions of a large number of individuals is trail shortening. Ants are famous for the ability to gradually decrease the length of their pheromone trail so that it finally draws a geodesic between the food source and the nest (Feynmann, 1985). This process can occur by the accumulated effect of ants that leave the trail (Deneubourg et al., 1983) and return to it a short distance away. Useful detours – those that ‘cut a corner’ and slightly decrease the trail's length – are then amplified by the group, while non-useful detours are abandoned (Deneubourg et al., 1983; Goss et al., 1989; Reid et al., 2011).
Even though trail shortening utilizes segments that were offered by individual ants, it is inherently different from the amplification schemes described in the previous section. This difference is manifested in the fact that the previous examples require the informed ant to ‘know that she knows’ and assess the quality of the information that she holds. Conversely, during trail shortening, ants that mark short-cuts are not required to hold any knowledge about the quality of their solutions. Rather, it is the group that either amplifies or eventually ignores this alternative trail segments through a pheromone-based positive-feedback mechanism.
Emergent collective cognition
So far, we have focused on group-level behaviors that gain their computational power by amplifying the actions and decisions of individuals. This differs from the notion of emergent cognition wherein collective scale processes allow the group to qualitatively transcend individual capabilities.
An intuitive example for the emergence of collective cognition is the transition between the different physical phases of matter. Minimal changes in temperature or the coupling between microscopic particles leads to qualitatively different macroscopic phases (e.g. the solid to liquid transition). It is therefore interesting to ask whether grouping together, not simple inanimate particles, but rather cognitive individuals with a memory and complex behavioral rules can be expected to display different and perhaps higher forms of emergence. Specifically, what forms of cognitive emergence occur in the case of social insects? In this section, we list several examples for emergent collective actions. As before, the examples are loosely ordered according to the increasing gaps between the individual and the group.
Weighted response to multiple stimuli
Since they are grouped into large ensembles, individual insects are, inevitably, much smaller than the size of the colony and its territory. As a consequence, individuals cannot have direct access to large-scale environmental and internal colony conditions. Despite this, the colony as a whole must react to the full set of stimuli and appropriately divide the work force (Robinson, 1992). Models suggest that colony-level division of labor can result from single insects with different task thresholds (Beshers and Fewell, 2001; Bonabeau, 1996) that resolve work demands which they locally experience (Franks and Tofts, 1994). Similar to the house-hunting example described above, this colony-level phenomenon relies on the cognitive assessments of individuals. The difference being that, in this case, the colony does not form a consensus around the solution of a single individual but rather divides the work force in a weighted manner according to information that is too spread out to be available to any one individual. Division of labor can include more complex mechanisms, such as recruitment, that allow ants to use not only personal but also social information to inform their decisions (Robinson et al., 2009a).
Partial decoupling between individual and collective scales
Cooperative transport is the process by which a group of ants retrieves a food item much too large for any of them to move on their own. During this process, the information available to individuals may be plainly misleading and counterproductive for the group's collective goals. This happens when trajectories to the nest as experienced by the small ants may be inaccessible to the large loads and even take it towards dead-ends that are difficult to escape. It was shown that to avoid such deadlocks, the macroscopic scale occasionally decouples from the possibly misleading information available at the microscopic scale (Fonio et al., 2016). This mechanism allows the group to utilize beneficial information while using noise present at the group level to escape deadlocks (local minima) and avoid the potentially devastating consequences of fully relying on misleading information. Importantly, such decoupling does not require that any single individual detects at any point in time, whether information is valuable or misleading.
Emergence in this system is evident as a separation between collective and individual behavior. This is evident as the carrying group (and the food item they transport) does not follow a trajectory that was suggested by any single ant.
Collective responses independent of individual actions
In some cases, the group can display effective reactions to stimuli that are not conceived by any individual. Such can be the case in which a cooperatively carrying group hits an obstacle. In such instances, instead of attempting to advance directly towards the nest, the group decouples from the actions of its individual members and goes into a perpendicular motion that takes the carried piece of food towards the edges of the obstacle (Gelblum et al., 2015). It was shown that this change in collective motion does not require any individual ant to be aware of the obstacle and individually change her behavior (Gelblum et al., 2016). Rather, the physical constraint induced by the obstacle directly affects the group as a whole. As a response, the group's mode of motion changes in a way that facilitates obstacle circumvention.
Self-organization without a blueprint
A final example for emergent behavior involves nest construction. Social insects construct some of the most magnificent structures in the biological world (Theraulaz et al., 2003). This is done through a stigmergic process (Theraulaz and Bonabeau, 1999) in which individuals locally interact with features of the structure by adding (or removing, in the case of dug nests) building material to them (Franks and Deneubourg, 1997). This induces indirect communication as insects interact with the product of the action of their nest-mates. It was further shown that, in some cases, building materials are combined with a volatile construction pheromone (Khuong et al., 2016). This adds a temporal dimension to the physical structure and expands the possibilities for local rules and the complexity of the resulting structure (Khuong et al., 2016).
In contrast to trail formation, for example, where the result of the collective effort is a refinement of almost complete structures suggested by individual ants, nest construction creates structures that appear to be far from the capabilities of any individual. Indeed, in this high form of emergence, it is unlikely that individuals have a blueprint of the desired final product. Nevertheless, they follow local rules and their collective effort results in the construction of intricate nests.
Sources of collective cognition
In this section we summarize the examples presented above including the advantages and challenges associated with the different sources of collective cognition. We then raise and discuss some hypotheses regarding the prevalence of collective-scale behaviors that strongly rely on the cognitive capabilities of individuals.
The individual-based collective cognition
An important factor to note is that many of the immediate requirements of the social group coincide with those of the individuals that constitute the group. Like the solitary insect, the colony must also scan the environment for food (Gordon, 1995), locate shelters (Franks et al., 2002), transport food (Gelblum et al., 2015), confront predators (Lamon and Topoff, 1981; Seeley et al., 1982) and care for brood (Siveter et al., 2014; Wang et al., 2015). As noted above, the cognitive abilities of individuals in a colony do not seem to greatly differ from those of their solitary counterparts. As such, the cognition of individuals within a colony hold direct advantages to the group as a whole. The section entitled ‘Individual-based collective cognition’ above provides examples wherein the actions of a single individual suffice for directing the entire colony.
Generally speaking, amplifying of the behavior of an individual requires two colony-level processes: the identification of the specific individual of interest and the amplification of its behavior. For example, as mentioned above, the first ant to find a food source has the capacity to trace the complete path between the nest and the food (Cammaerts and Cammaerts, 1980; Hölldobler, 1976; Wilson, 1962). This ant makes itself identifiable by laying pheromone markings on the surface as it heads back to the nest (Beckers et al., 1992a). Amplification occurs as ants that follow this trail enforce it with further pheromonal markings. Finally, mass foraging develops along the trail drawn out by the initial recruiting ant (Beckers et al., 1989). In many cases, solutions provided by different individuals are in conflict such that if one solution is amplified, this must come at the expense of others. In this case, a third decision-making process occurs alongside identification and amplification. Some mechanisms by which such collective decisions occur include the preferential reinforcement of preferred solutions, such as preferred food sources being marked by higher pheromone concentrations (Beckers et al., 1992b; Jaffe and Howse, 1979; Sumpter and Beekman, 2003) and cross-inhibition between alternative emerging solutions, as occurs during honeybee recruitment (Nieh, 2010).
The group
It is not always the case that an individual insect holds the complete solution to the colony's current needs. In fact, inherent constraints work to limit the value of individually held information. A first constraint involves the size of the individual when compared with that of its colony. Colonies reside over territories that are tens of meters (in the case of ants) or even kilometers (for wasps and bees) across and include large elaborate nest structures on a scale of several meters (Tschinkel, 2004). It is impossible for a single individual whose size is in the order of one centimeter to individually monitor these large areas. Other constraints are an individual's propensity to be badly informed, mistakenly wrong or limited by its cognitive capacity (Sasaki and Pratt, 2012).
The second set of examples as above highlights behaviors in which the group holds useful information about the environment but this information is distributed among a large number of individuals. Using communication, these information fragments can be integrated to yield collective decisions that take the ‘big picture’ into account. Such integration can often be classified using two general schemes defined for animal groups in general: the ‘many eyes principle’ (Ward et al., 2011) in which the group's capacity for surveillance increases with the number of alert animals and the ‘many wrongs principle’ (Biro et al., 2006; Simons, 2004) in which averaging effects work to reduce ‘noise’ at the scale of an individual animal to yield accurate collective action. Integration of information occurs over a large number of contexts and species. Some recurring principles in this process include: distributed integration, nonlinearities (Sumpter and Beekman, 2003), positive and negative feedback loops (Franks et al., 2002; Nieh, 2010), use of interaction rates and cuing delays (Camazine, 1993; Greene et al., 2013), higher influence and lower propensity to be influenced by better-informed individuals (Korman et al., 2014; Razin et al., 2013; Schultz et al., 2008) and correctly weighing individual versus social information (Robinson et al., 2009b, 2012).
This section also presents examples in which colonies have evolved to achieve a collective task by amplifying the behaviors of individuals that work towards the small-scale version of this same task. For example, in the context of cooperative transport the actions of a leader ant are exactly those she would take when individually transporting a small food item to the nest. The group allows these actions to be the driving force behind the transport of a large heavy item.
The network
Last, some colony functions may fall outside the solitary insect's behavioral or cognitive repertoire. These include large-scale behaviors, such as assessing the relationship between the size of two objects when both of these are much larger than the insect itself (Fonio et al., 2016; Gelblum et al., 2016) and active dissemination of food (Camazine, 1993; Greenwald et al., 2015; Howard and Tschinkel, 1981). In such cases, to achieve the group-level task, the relevant capabilities must arise either by newly evolved individual traits or through a collective process that relies on the connectivity between individuals (a combination of these two options is also possible). Cases in which group-level processes bestow the group with abilities that are qualitatively beyond those of its individual members can, by definition (De Wolf and Holvoet, 2005), be considered as a form of emergence.
In the two examples of cooperative transport presented above, group problem-solving capabilities increase beyond those of individuals. In these cases, the small size of individual insects may prevent it from grasping the relevant large-scale relationships between the carried load and the obstacle. Therefore, in these cases, the problem-solving at the level of the group must decouple to some extent from the array of, possibly misleading, solutions as offered by individuals, even if these are highly adept navigators. The mechanisms that enable such decoupling between the scales do not have to be complex. In these examples, group-level noise in following scent marks (Fonio et al., 2016) and the persistence that results from alignment of forces (Gelblum et al., 2016) suffice for efficient transport that interacts with the environment on the relevant scale of the ant team and the large carried load.
Stigmergic nest construction holds the potential for higher levels of emergence. Here, nest construction is carried out by individuals that follow simple local rules while constantly reacting to the environmental product of their previous actions (Grassé, 1959). Following these stigmergic principles may allow insects to construct elaborate nest architectures (Theraulaz et al., 2003; Tschinkel, 2004) without any blueprint. The degree of emergence in such processes is difficult to define. On the one hand, by using a stigmergic process, a single insect such as a solitary queen may construct a structure for which it holds no internal representation (Camazine et al., 2003; Theraulaz and Bonabeau, 1999). A larger group in which each individual follows the same rules may achieve faster construction but the quality of emergence remains constant (Theraulaz and Bonabeau, 1999). On the other hand, it has been shown that pheromone deposition onto the constructed nest is an essential part of collective stigmergic nest construction. The addition of this time-dependent component (pheromones evaporate) has the potential of allowing the group to achieve more complex forms of emergence not achievable by a single individual working alone (Khuong et al., 2016). Indeed, such processes can be modeled using the mathematics of cellular automata, a theory which holds the potential of describing extreme forms of emergence (Wolfram, 2002).
Prevalence of individual-based mechanisms
Next, we raise some hypotheses in an attempt to provide rationale for the observed imminence of individuals to colony-scale processes.
As shown above, colony-level behaviors are often a consequence of the direct amplification of individual actions that rely on individual cognition. This did not have to be the case. One could imagine an evolutionary pathway where collective cognition is constructed from a network of different individuals each manifesting different, possibly more basic, capabilities. In this case, the actions of individuals do not directly coincide with the actions of the group or even with each other. Rather, group performance emerges from the coordination between individuals. An example of this is neurons in the brain. Neurons have evolved to be cells whose actions are purely computational such that their spiking activity bears no direct relationship to the collective process in which they participate. Hypothetically, there is no established reason why such computational hierarchies would not arise in a social insect colony and serve as the basis for highly efficient collective-scale behaviors. Why, therefore, is this not the general case?
We suggest that the first part of the answer to this question has to do with the availability and high-quality performances that individual-based group-level cognition can achieve. As stated above, by the time group cognition had evolved, individual insects had already developed as independent organisms (Farris and Schulmeister, 2011; Ma et al., 2012). As such, they already possessed many of the cognitive resources that are required by the group. Furthermore, these individual capabilities are, in no sense, simple. For example, individual insects are highly adept navigators. To get from one place to another individual insects employ a toolbox consisting of multiple tactics, often applied in parallel. Across different insects, these include landmark navigation (Collett et al., 1993), dead reckoning (Collett and Collett, 2000), backtracking (Wystrach et al., 2013) and cognitive map (Gould, 1986) navigation by means of scents (Morgan, 2009), visual cues (Collett et al., 1993; Esch et al., 2001; Wehner, 2003), temperature, and even magnetic fields. Collective cognition that relies on such individual capabilities holds the advantage of utilizing these highly non-trivial traits.
The fact that individual insects possess high cognitive capabilities does not, however, suffice in explaining why these capabilities take a central role in many collective-level processes. In the context of the navigation example as in the previous paragraph, it may very well be the case that a navigational toolbox that relies on the distributed actions of a large number of cooperating insects not only exists but, also outperforms other individual-based schemes. Again, one may ask why this is not the general case and why the role of individuals has remained so pronounced throughout evolution. We hypothesize that the answer to this question has to do with the complexity of efficient distributed solutions given the inherent constraints that apply for a colony of autonomous individuals. We suggest that in many cases, simple distributed algorithms would not outperform what is readily achievable by amplifying individual cognition. We further hypothesize that distributed algorithms that do surpass simpler amplification processes may be expected to be highly complex and therefore difficult to evolve. Hence, the system may be trapped within local minima within the fitness landscape, which utilize the individual cognitive components that have evolved at earlier stages. The next section discusses some of the non-trivial limitations on emergent behavioral solutions.
Computational constraints on emergent collective cognition
Emergence is often associated with the notion of a group that ‘exceeds the sum of its parts’. Theoretically speaking, achieving such highly effective cooperation typically requires a substantial degree of coordination. An intuitive example for this is the parallel search problem in which a group of non-communicating random walkers that start at a given location aim to collectively cover an area and then share the profits of their findings. In this context, to ‘exceed the sum of its parts’ implies that the group of N searchers cover the area more than N times faster than each individual were it acting on its own. In fact, in many natural topologies (Alon et al., 2011; Efremenko and Reingold, 2009), the situation is very far from this. For example, in grid topologies when searchers do not communicate and as long as N is not too small, multiple random walks that start from a single point, typically achieve negligible speed-up in cover time when compared with a single searcher (Alon et al., 2011) (i.e. the group takes almost as much time to cover an area as a single one of its members). In this case, being part of a group becomes highly unbeneficial from an individual's point of view: food must be shared but without the advantage of obtaining it at a faster rate.
Biological systems often achieve emergence using involved communication. The most celebrated example for this is that of the brain, viewed as a large ensemble of neurons. In the case of brains, such coordination heavily relies on the fact that the neurons are organized into stable networks such that the set of neighboring neurons of a given neuron remains, relatively, fixed. Synaptic plasticity allows a pair of neighboring neurons to undergo a mutual feedback process and fine-tune their connectivity (Hebb, 1949). This, as conceptually demonstrated by the Hopfield model (Hopfield, 1982), may provide the system with its immense computational power. Indeed, Hopfield networks have been shown to be capable of universal computation in the Turing sense (Síma and Orponen, 2003).
What can one expect for social insect colonies? On the one hand, these are very far from being non-communicating. On the other hand, interaction networks appear to be more loosely defined than those that characterize a brain. Indeed, in the insect colony, fixed organization structures may be difficult to achieve for long periods of time owing to the inherent mobility and anonymity constraints. This lack of structure leads to a lack of knowledge that further constrains the system (Burgos and Polani, 2016). Namely, while learning in the brain happens by strengthening the synaptic connections between pairs of specific hard-wired (and therefore mutually identifiable) neurons, it is difficult to imagine such mechanisms for freely moving, anonymous insects. Furthermore, many brain functions are known to depend on precise interaction patterns that enable, for example, high levels of synchrony (Abeles, 1991). Such preciseness is difficult to imagine in the case of autonomous independent agents.
It appears that things become even worse if communication and information flows across the systems are, themselves, limited or distorted (Feinerman and Korman, 2012; Feinerman et al., 2014; Korman et al., 2014; Razin et al., 2013). The highly dynamic environment and interchanging network structures that characterize the social insect colony make it difficult to implement error-correcting mechanisms such as repeatedly sending the same message in order to reduce distortion. As demonstrated previously (Feinerman and Korman, 2012; Feinerman et al., 2014; Korman et al., 2014; Razin et al., 2013), such circumstances make even basic distributed tasks, such as rumor spreading, challenging. It is therefore reasonable to assume that emergent phenomena would be even more difficult to implement in such conditions.
Summary
Useful information exists at the level of the individual insect. This often suffices for the group's needs and indeed, we have presented many examples in which the group follows individuals by amplifying their effect. In other cases, the inherent scale gap between individual and group may render information held by individuals partial, irrelevant or even misleading to the collective goals of the group. In such cases, emergent collective phenomena may take effect. Cognition that emerges at the level of the colony is subject to multiple constraints that mainly result from the fact that individuals maintain their autonomy as insects within the colony. Indeed, the most complex collective circuits described to date (Nieh, 2010; Pratt et al., 2005; Seeley et al., 2012) may be defined as simple when compared with the neural circuits that allow, for example, an ant to find her nest by using vector integration (Ofstad et al., 2011; Wehner, 2003).
Interestingly, the ways in which collective cognition appears, even during a single behavior, are not mutually exclusive. An example for this comes from cooperative transport in Paratrechina longicornis ants. Indeed, during this behavior, the ants simultaneously benefit from both individual-based (Gelblum et al., 2015) and collective-based cognition (Fonio et al., 2016; Gelblum et al., 2016). This balance between the organizational scales allows the system to enjoy the best of both the macroscopic and the microscopic worlds.
Forming better connections between different collective behaviors and the levels of emergence that characterize them requires further research. We suggest that such research should be focused in two distinct areas. The first is a computational study of the powers and limitations of natural distributed algorithms (Feinerman et al., 2014; Greenwald et al., 2015). Specifically, there is a need to better understand the complexity and evolvability of distributed solutions of different qualities. The second avenue involves empirical studies that attempt to trace the evolution of emergent, communication-based solutions. An example for this direction could be a comparative study of nest structures across a large number of phylogenetically related ant or termite species.
Acknowledgements
A.K. and O.F. thank Yossi Yovel and Ehud Fonio for comments on this manuscript.
Footnotes
Funding
This work received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union's Horizon 2020 research and innovation program (648032). O.F. is the incumbent of the Shlomo and Michla Tomarin Career Development Chair and is supported by the Israel Science Foundation (833/15) and the ongoing generosity of the Clore Foundation.
References
Competing interests
The authors declare no competing or financial interests.