Summary
This paper presents an overview of how mechanistic knowledge of organism–environment interactions, including biomechanical interactions of heat, mass and momentum transfer, can be integrated into basic theoretical population biology through mechanistic functional responses that quantitatively describe how organisms respond to their physical environment. Integrating such functional responses into simple community and microevolutionary models allows scaling up of the organism-level understanding from biomechanics both ecologically and temporally. For community models, Holling-type functional responses for predator–prey interactions provide a classic example of the functional response affecting qualitative model dynamics, and recent efforts are expanding analogous models to incorporate environmental influences such as temperature. For evolutionary models, mechanistic functional responses dependent on the environment can serve as fitness functions in both quantitative genetic and game theoretic frameworks, especially those concerning function-valued traits. I present a novel comparison of a mechanistic fitness function based on thermal performance curves to a commonly used generic fitness function, which quantitatively differ in their predictions for response to environmental change. A variety of examples illustrate how mechanistic functional responses enhance model connections to biologically relevant traits and processes as well as environmental conditions and therefore have the potential to link theoretical and empirical studies. Sensitivity analysis of such models can provide biologically relevant insight into which parameters and processes are important to community and evolutionary responses to environmental change such as climate change, which can inform conservation management aimed at protecting response capacity. Overall, the distillation of detailed knowledge or organism–environment interactions into mechanistic functional responses in simple population biology models provides a framework for integrating biomechanics and ecology that allows both tractability and generality.
Introduction
As described by Denny and Helmuth (Denny and Helmuth, 2009), integrating biomechanics and ecology represents a scaling up from the biomechanics of individual organisms and their interaction with their environment to the ecology of populations and communities. A full population biology understanding requires extension of biomechanics in two dimensions. In the ecological dimension, scaling up from populations to interacting species provides a community- and ecosystem-level understanding rooted in mechanistic knowledge. In the temporal dimension, scaling up from ecological to evolutionary time provides an evolutionary understanding also rooted in mechanistic knowledge of organisms’ interactions with their environment.
This pursuit of understanding the interaction between patterns across multiple scales is central to the field of ecology and evolutionary biology and its application to management, and theory and models play a key role in cross-scale extrapolation (Levin, 1992). Models serve a number of purposes in population biology (and in general), with the goal of a model determining whether it is constructed as a general, phenomenological or detailed mechanistic model. Levins translates the range of possible model structures into a trade-off between generality, realism and precision (Levins, 1966). Here, the distinction between precision and realism is akin to that between precision and accuracy: quantitatively exact and consistent values versus closeness to the actual (real-world) value. Within this trade-off, Levins suggests that one of the three properties is typically sacrificed in favor of the other two, and the two focal properties dictate the potential model contribution (Levins, 1966). In particular, (1) focusing on realism and precision at the expense of generality leads to the potential for testable predictions for a specific situation, (2) focusing on generality and realism at the expense of precision leads to the capacity for qualitative predictions about different possible outcomes, and (3) focusing on generality and precision at the expense of realism leads to null-type models that allow exploration of how the incremental addition of realism affects overall dynamics.
Much of the basic theory of population biology focuses on the generality side of this trade-off, where the goal might be to formalize a hypothesis about the factors driving a given outcome in a mathematical framework to rigorously test and quantify the underlying logical expectations (i.e. mathematics as ‘a way of thinking clearly’) (May, 2004). In contrast, biomechanics, including that integrated with ecology, is rooted in a bottom-up approach focusing on detailed mechanisms (Denny and Helmuth, 2009) and therefore gravitates towards the realism side of this trade-off. A number of modeling frameworks, described elsewhere in this special issue of The Journal of Experimental Biology, follow the biomechanics approach of scaling up from mechanistic physiological [e.g. dynamic energy budget models (Nisbet et al., 2012)] or individual-level [e.g. scale-transition and complexity theory (Benedetti-Cecchi et al., 2012; Van de Koppel et al., 2012)] dynamics to patterns on ecological scales.
In addition to building up directly from the mechanistic knowledge itself and therefore starting with realism, another approach to integrating biomechanics or analogous mechanistic knowledge with theoretical population biology is to start with more general models from basic theory and incrementally add realism based on the mechanistic understanding. Specifically, one approach is to distill mechanistic understanding of organism–environment interactions into a functional response that can fit into the framework of more generic and tractable models of theoretical population biology. Mechanistic functional responses, in particular those that quantitatively describe how an organism or population responds to an environmental variable, represent a key component to the scaling-up process inherent to integrating biomechanics and ecology (Denny and Benedetti-Cecchi, in review). This approach takes advantage of the biological realism that stems from biomechanics and allows integration of that mechanistic, detailed understanding into a tractable framework where central dynamics and drivers can more easily be discerned.
Here, I describe how mechanistic functional responses that describe organism–environment interactions can be integrated into basic community and evolutionary ecological models. While others have proposed the use of mechanistic functional responses in models of community and evolutionary ecology (typically treated separately) [(e.g. Arnold, 1983; Schoener, 1986; Denny and Benedetti-Cecchi, in review) see also additional citations throughout this manuscript], the goal of this manuscript is to provide an accessible outline of how to approach this task in both subdisciplines. Therefore, this manuscript serves as an overview rather than a comprehensive review. In addition, a specific focus here is on incorporating mechanistic knowledge pertaining to how organisms interact with their environment, which includes but is not limited to the biomechanical interactions of heat, momentum and mass transfer (Denny and Helmuth, 2009).
This functional response-based approach can apply to additional modeling frameworks from basic theoretical population biology not covered here such as non-evolutionary single-population dynamics, including stage- or physiologically structured dynamics. Also, scaling up in space receives only superficial attention here. The focus here on community and evolutionary ecology is intended to provide an illustration of the general approach centered on the scaling up of biomechanics ecologically and temporally. In addition, it complements the population models presented elsewhere in this special issue, such as the structured population models of Nisbet et al. and Madin and Connolly (Nisbet et al., 2012; Madin and Connolly, 2012) as well as the models focused on scaling up community dynamics in space discussed by Benedetti-Cecchi et al. and Van de Koppel et al. (Benedetti-Cecchi et al., 2012; Van de Koppel et al., 2012).
In order to start with the simplest possible models within community and evolutionary ecology, below I describe the potential integration of biomechanics into basic non-evolutionary multi-species models and microevolutionary single-species models through mechanistic functional responses, defined more specifically in each context. For each I provide the general frameworks and illustrative examples, from a classic example for community ecology to a novel example for evolutionary ecology. Throughout I highlight how this approach mechanistically adds an environmental dimension to population dynamics to provide insight into when mechanism matters to the qualitative or quantitative outcome, connect models to biologically relevant, empirically measurable parameters, and allow exploration of dynamical responses to different environmental conditions. Finally, I outline the potential for this understanding to inform conservation biology through a mechanistic understanding of the central drivers of ecological and evolutionary response to environmental change.
Community ecology
In this section, I first describe a classic, textbook example of how the shape of the functional response affects the dynamics of interacting species in a basic predator–prey model. Then I discuss ways that mechanistic knowledge of organism–environment interactions can factor into the functional forms of predator–prey models, with a Boltzmann factor-based approach of incorporating temperature effects on predator–prey dynamics as an example. Finally, I discuss how this approach might apply more broadly to general models of interacting species and highlight connections to the frameworks of trait-mediated interactions and ecosystem engineering.
Classic functional response example in predator–prey interactions
These three functional responses lead to qualitatively different model outcomes. For type I, the system is always stable (predators and prey haven damped oscillations towards a fixed point; Fig. 1D). For type II, either unstable or stable dynamics is possible depending on the parameter values, with stabilization at parameter values that yield higher equilibrium prey densities (Fig. 1E). For type III, again either unstable or stable dynamics is possible depending on parameter values, but in this case stabilization occurs at parameter values that yield lower or higher equilibrium prey densities with unstable dynamics (e.g. limit cycles) occurring at intermediate prey densities (Fig. 1E).
Adding mechanistic functional responses to predator–prey models and Boltzmann factor example
While the example of the three Holling functional responses demonstrates the potential importance of the function shape, the type I–III functional responses are relatively phenomenological (i.e. have a general functional form that resembles empirical patterns, as opposed to the functional form being mechanistically derived from first principles). Mechanistic knowledge can factor into determining which predator–prey functional response might apply among these three or the variety of other possibilities such as those based on predator interference (e.g. Skalski and Gilliam, 2001), herbivore grazing dynamics (e.g. Spalinger and Hobbs, 1992) and ratio (P/H) dependence (e.g. Berryman, 1992). While the saturating type II functional response is the most commonly used in basic community models, data from predator–prey dynamics more often have a better fit to functional responses that are based on predator interference, where the functional response depends on predator as well as prey density (Spalinger and Hobbs, 1992).
In addition, Holling-type functional responses are narrowly concerned with the effects of prey density on the rate of prey capture. Mechanistic consideration of organism–environment interactions, including those relevant to biomechanics, requires extension of this framework to incorporate a broader class of mechanistic response functions in which the independent variable can be any aspect of the environment (either biotic or abiotic). For example, Vasseur and McCann incorporate temperature (a key environmental characteristic) into a predator–prey model with Holling type II (i.e. saturating) predation rate based on first principles of thermodynamics (Vasseur and McCann, 2005). According to a relationship first defined by Boltzmann, the rate of any chemical reaction is governed by the ratio of its activation energy, Ei, to the energy available from molecular collisions, κT, where κ is Boltzmann’s constant and T is absolute temperature. Specifically, the rate is proportional to e–Ei/(κT); the higher the temperature, the faster the rate. This mechanistically determined proportionality is the basis for the Q10 effects traditionally measured by physiologists.
In addition, the authors express the predator efficiency factor in Eqn 2 as c=fe(1–δ). While this formulation adds many new parameters, including some that could be consolidated if symbolic mathematical analysis were the only consideration, the mechanistic basis allows for more straightforward biological interpretation of the parameters and parameterization from empirical data. In addition, the model structure maintains enough simplicity to remain tractable, in particular allowing analytical expressions for the dynamical change in each of the prey and predator with temperature (dH/dT and dP/dT).
Because the basic dynamical structure of the model remains the same, no new dynamics emerge from the inclusion of this temperature dependence, unlike the Holling-type functional responses described above. Rather, it adds a new dimension to the model by allowing exploration of how temperature will affect which of the possible dynamical outcomes (stable node or cyclical behavior as illustrated in Fig. 1E) occurs. The mechanistic basis of this added dimension provides a concrete foundation for exploring the interactive effects of temperature dependence in three different aspects of the predator–prey dynamics (prey production, predator ingestion and predator respiration), the complexity of which would limit any phenomenological consideration. In particular, from their analysis of the model, Vasseur and McCann find that increasing temperatures destabilize predator–prey dynamics, lead to decreases in prey biomass, and lead to greater changes in predator than prey biomass (Vasseur and McCann, 2005).
Rall and colleagues employ a similar Boltzmann factor-based approach of exploring the effect of temperature changes on the predator–prey model in Eqns 1 and 2, but with a linear, type I Holling functional response for the predation rate and temperature dependence in the prey carrying capacity K as well as the prey growth and the predator ingestion rates (Rall et al., 2010). Again, the overall equilibrium dynamics remain the same (stable node as in Fig. 1D), but the inclusion of complex temperature effects on multiple processes allows exploration of this new dimension and reveals that increasing temperature leads to decreasing equilibrium interaction strength between the predator and prey. Both examples illustrate the potential for the inclusion of mechanistic functional responses that describe organism–environment interactions in relatively simple dynamical models to elucidate how environmental change might affect the dynamics of the interacting species. In addition, both studies exemplify the potential for connection to empirical data given mechanistically based, biologically relevant parameters: Rall and colleagues parameterize their model based on terrestrial arthropod experiments (Rall et al., 2010), and Vasseur and McCann provide a variety of parameterizations based on vertebrate ectotherm and marine invertebrate systems (Vasseur and McCann, 2005).
Community models more generally
As with the predator–prey case, a mechanistic understanding can inform the functional form of both interspecific [gi(Ni,Nj)] and intraspecific [fi(Ni)] dynamics. The general idea of building mechanistic functional responses for interspecific interactions overlaps with the framework of trait-mediated interactions, which extends the typical consideration of population density-dependent species interactions to also include the role of individual traits, and the traits that influence species interactions can be morphological, behavioral or life history (reviewed by Bolker et al., 2003). The theory of trait-mediated interactions indicates the importance of the shape of functional responses to population dynamics, but such shapes are rarely measured to construct empirically driven models (Bolker et al., 2003).
Mechanistic functional responses hold the potential to fill this crucial knowledge gap to connect theory and data as well as extend this theory to incorporate the interaction between organisms and their environment. As mentioned above, mechanistic functional responses that incorporate dependence on the abiotic environment add another dimension to allow understanding of how environmental drivers affect the dynamical outcome. For example, the Boltzmann factor framework described in the context of predator–prey models above (e.g. Vasseur and McCann, 2005) has the potential to provide a general approach for incorporating temperature dependence into the dynamics of interacting species. In addition, dispersal kernels as they depend on abiotic conditions (e.g. wind or currents, discussed in more detail in ‘Game theory and dispersal evolution example’ below) represent a type of functional response based on organism–environment interactions that can provide insight into the co-existence of competing species (e.g. Berkley et al., 2010).
More generally, consideration of dynamical resource dependence on the biotic environment falls within the framework of ecosystem engineering (Jones et al., 1994). In other words, the functional form of the response of the abiotic environment to the density of an ecosystem engineer can be considered a type of environmental functional response. The theory of ecosystem engineering indicates that explicit consideration of organism-dependent resource dynamics, and therefore biotic environmental functional responses for resources, is most important when the organism–resource interaction dynamics occur on larger spatial and temporal scales than the intra- and/or inter-specific dynamics (Hastings et al., 2007). Models that incorporate this type of environmental functional response demonstrate the importance of ecosystem engineering to ecological dynamics such as population persistence, invasive species spread and spatial dynamics (reviewed by Hastings et al., 2007).
Overall, different functions for intraspecific and interspecific dynamics readily affect the outcome of community ecology models, and a mechanistic approach to developing such functions can both connect the parameters to biologically relevant and measurable processes and provide an indication of the appropriate functional response for a given system (Schoener, 1986). Focusing on functional traits as they affect performance under different environmental conditions has the potential to enhance the quantitative and predictive content of community ecology theory (McGill et al., 2006). Furthermore, the incorporation of a more bottom-up, mechanistic approach in multispecies models is in line with recent suggestions to build community ecology up from the processes that drive community-level patterns (rather than the top-down approach of starting with the patterns themselves), which Roughgarden (Roughgarden, 2009) and Vellend (Vellend, 2010) posit has a greater potential to lead to a general theory of community ecology.
Evolutionary ecology
In the community models described above, mechanistic knowledge about organisms’ interactions with their environment could factor into an environment-dependent functional response for a variety of dynamics, from intraspecific dynamics such as population growth rate to interaction dynamics such as predation rate. For a single-species model of evolutionary change, it is the mechanistic functional response in terms of the environment-dependent population growth rate (i.e. function that describes how the population growth rate responds to the environment) that holds particular relevance as it provides a metric of fitness. If this function appropriately describes both population growth and fitness, then it can serve to couple ecological and evolutionary dynamics.
Below, I describe two broad frameworks for integrating such a mechanistic functional response into evolutionary dynamics: quantitative genetics (with two modeling approaches described) and game theory. This is not intended to be an exhaustive accounting of all models relevant to these frameworks but rather an example illustration of a handful of commonly used models. The focus here is on the microevolutionary dynamics of changing gene frequencies within a population rather than the macroevolutionary processes of speciation and extinction because microevolution has greater ecological relevance and is therefore more relevant to this special issue. In addition, for simplicity, this section focuses on single-species models; for an integrative review of both population genetic and game theoretic frameworks in the context of co-evolutionary questions of evolutionary ecology, see Abrams (Abrams, 2001) and Day (Day, 2005).
In addition to describing the generic mathematical formulations with an indication of which term can be an environment-dependent functional response in all cases, for the first quantitative genetics modeling approach I discuss existing theoretical constructs (specifically, the phenotype–performance–fitness framework and function-valued traits) that are particularly relevant to the integration of biomechanics. For the second quantitative genetics modeling approach I analyze an example based on the evolution of thermal tolerance in a changing environment in order to illustrate the mechanistic functional response approach. Finally, for the game theory approach I use a discussion of dispersal, a topic often explored in both game theory and biomechanics, to exemplify how a biomechanics-based understanding might shift the focus of evolutionary models and allow better integration of models with data.
Quantitative genetics
Population genetic models follow gene frequencies over time as they depend on relative fitness, which encompasses both survivorship and reproductive success. While the simplest possible model construction of density-independent fitness leads to genetic dynamics independent of population dynamics (i.e. gene frequency dynamics do not depend on population size), the average population fitness (relative frequency of each genotype multiplied by its fitness, then summed over all possible genotypes) could be considered a metric of the population growth rate, thus coupling the population (ecological) dynamics to the genetic (evolutionary) dynamics. In addition, consideration of density-dependent influences on fitness inevitably leads to population size-dependent genotype fitness and therefore necessitates fully coupled population and genetic dynamics (Day, 2005).
A mechanistic understanding of organism–environment interactions can underlie the quantification of fitness in population genetic models. For example, a physiological understanding of organism response to the physical environment and how that affects investment in growth, maintenance and reproduction can allow measurement of the fitness for the traits relevant to that process. This measurement of fitness for different traits could directly provide the parameters for a Mendelian (i.e. discrete phenotypes) model of population genetics, such as a one-locus, two-allele model where fitness is defined separately for each genotype as a distinct parameter.
However, traits relevant to mechanistic knowledge (including biomechanics-based knowledge), such as morphological and physiological traits, are typically quantitative genetic traits: they can take on a continuum of values that depend on multiple contributing genes as well as the environment. One approach to modeling such traits is to follow the continuous probability density function pz(z) of phenotype z [i.e. pz(z)dz describes the proportion of the population with phenotypes between z and z+dz] and/or the probability density py(y) of genotype y, where both the genotypes and the phenotypes are continuous variables (the mathematical description of the link between the two is described in more detail below; the genetic probability density can also be considered the ‘breeding value’ distribution). Then the fitness function Wz(z) that drives adaptive dynamics is also a continuous function that describes how fitness depends on phenotype z; note that here and throughout I use y and z subscripts to the probability density and fitness functions to indicate whether they are functions of genotypes or phenotypes, respectively. Often, fitness functions have phenomenological functional forms for generality and tractability (e.g. general representations of stabilizing, disruptive or directional selection) (Lande and Arnold, 1983) or occasionally are determined from fits to empirical data (e.g. Schluter, 1988), but they can also be built up from mechanistic knowledge.
As a demonstration of where fitness functions integrate into models of coupled population and genetic dynamics, including example fitness functions to provide a more concrete illustration, I use two different models: a discrete-time, diploid model with sexual reproduction and a continuous-time, haploid model with asexual reproduction. Both are built on the ‘infinitesimal alleles’ assumption that a large number of unlinked loci contribute additively to the overall genotype y. Among the many possible population genetic frameworks [see, for example, Denny and Dowd in this issue for another quantitative genetic modeling framework (Denny and Dowd, 2012)], the two described here hold appeal for integrating biomechanics-based knowledge because they provide flexibility for the definition of the fitness function.
Discrete-time sexual model, the phenotype performance–fitness model, and function-valued traits
The discrete-time, diploid, sexual model follows the genotype probability density pt(y) at each point in time t assuming non-overlapping generations. The model dynamics consist of (1) applying selection and (2) mating and inheritance of genotypes, in either order. Selection occurs on the phenotype (z), but the genotype (y) is what is inherited in the ‘transmission function’ that describes the transmission of parental genotypes to the offspring.
Determining how selection affects the genotype distribution requires multiplying the genotype probability density pt(y) by the probability of having a particular phenotype given a particular genotype q(z|y), then multiplying by the phenotype-dependent fitness Wz(z) and integrating over all phenotypes. In other words, the genotype-dependent fitness is Wy(y)=∫Wz(z)q(z|y)dz (assuming one selection event per generation). For phenotypes randomly distributed around the genotypes with environmental variance VE, the phenotype–genotype probability function is the Gaussian function q(z|y)=exp[–(z–y)2/(2VE)]/√(2πVE) (i.e. given each genotype y, the probability density of phenotype z around that genotype is normal with a mean y and variance VE). Applying selection then requires multiplying the fitness by the genotype probability density [Wy(y)pt(y)] and normalizing such that the resulting distribution remains a probability density function. The normalization factor, the fitness of each genotype multiplied by its frequency integrated over all genotypes [∫Wy(y)pt(y)dy], is also the mean fitness of the population Wt.
Another approach to determining more realistic fitness functions is to build up the functional form from a mechanistic understanding. Many fitness-optimization models, including those rooted in energy budgets and their constraints (Weiner, 1992), provide such a functional form. While these models typically focus on determining the optimal trait, using such a fitness function in the framework of Eqns 16, 17, 18 provides a dynamical understanding of the trajectory of evolutionary change, which will depend both on the selection strength (determined by the shape of the fitness function) and population traits such as genetic variance. The qualitative outcome of evolution towards the selected trait at a rate dependent on selection strength and heritable variation will not differ from phenomenological fitness functions; however, a mechanistic fitness function’s basis in empirically measurable, biologically relevant parameters allows quantitative understanding of how specific biological processes affect the evolutionary trajectory and outcome.
A mechanistic underpinning to the fitness function more readily allows insight into the evolutionary response to different environmental conditions (Arnold, 2003), especially novel environmental conditions where direct empirical measurements of selection or fitness are not available. For such an exploration, the fitness function will depend on both the phenotype and the environment. A natural extension of the phenotype–performance–fitness framework mentioned above is to include the influence of the biotic and abiotic environment (i.e. habitat) on phenotype and performance (Garland and Losos, 1994). For example, Kingsolver and Gomulkiewicz use thermal performance functions to explore the effect of environmental variation on the evolution of performance (Kingsolver and Gomulkiewicz, 2003). Their framework, readily connected to experimental caterpillar data, provides unique insight into whether selection acts on total growth, integrated performance or growth rates in particular environments. This approach is an example of following the evolution of ‘function-valued traits’, or traits that are a continuous function of an organism’s status (e.g. age) or an environmental parameter (e.g. temperature); for the latter, following the evolution of the function is akin to following the evolution of phenotypic plasticity (Kingsolver et al., 2001). Modeling the evolution of function-valued traits can involve direct extension of the above-described approach to quantitative genetics (Kingsolver et al., 2001). In addition, new genetic and genomic tools to mechanistically explore fitness and plasticity (see Whitehead, 2012) are increasing the capacity to integrate this theory with data. An example of a model that incorporates such organism–environment interactions is provided in the next section on continuous-time asexual models.
Continuous-time asexual model and thermal tolerance example
Underlying these modeling efforts is often the more specific question of the rate of climate change a population can keep up with, in which case the changing environment typically can be considered in terms of changing temperature. For example, Huey and Kingsolver (Huey and Kingsolver, 1993) and Bonebrake and Mastrandrea (Bonebrake and Mastrandrea, 2010) apply the more generic models of Lynch and colleagues (Lynch and Lande, 1993; Lynch and Gabriel, 1987) to the evolution of thermal tolerance. These models retain symmetric fitness functions, such as the one specified above, for tractability. In reality, thermal performance curves tend to take a more asymmetrical form with a faster drop-off in population growth at higher temperatures than the temperature of peak performance, compared with lower temperatures than the peak (Angilletta et al., 2003).
As in the study by Lynch and colleagues (Lynch et al., 1991), I investigate the capacity for a population to adapt to a linearly changing environment, i.e. θ(t)=θ0+kt for different rates of environmental change k (Fig. 3). In the simulations that use the thermal performance curves, the potential for faster population growth rates with increasing temperatures does lead to faster evolutionary change (Fig. 3C, comparing dashed lines with solid lines of the same color). However, the faster decline in population growth at higher temperatures leads to earlier and greater likelihood of extinction rather than adaptation (Fig. 3D, again comparing dashed lines to solid lines of the same color). This example illustrates how a mechanistic fitness function can affect the quantitative predictions for adaptation to environmental change in ways that are difficult to predict.
Game theory and dispersal evolution example
The classic evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS) (sensuMaynard Smith and Price, 1973), or a strategy that cannot be invaded by any other strategy, is z* such that λ(z,z*)≤λ(z*,z*) for all z in this representation. Note that if λ is independent of z [i.e. no frequency dependence such that λ(z,zˆ)=λ(z)], this reduces to a question of fitness optimization [z that maximizes λ(z)]. In addition to the ability to withstand invasion, another dimension important to predicting the evolutionary outcome is the ability to invade when rare, here formalized as z* such that λ(z*,z)≥λ(z,z) for all z [termed the neighborhood invader strategy, or NIS, when considering nearby strategies (Apaloo, 1997)]. Plotting successful versus unsuccessful invasion for the full set of all pairwise combinations of invaders and residents in a ‘pairwise invasibility plot’ indicates the predicted evolutionary outcome [see Geritz et al. (Geritz et al., 1998) and Levin and Muller-Landau (Levin and Muller-Landau, 2000) for a full classification of evolutionary outcomes]. Expanding on this theory to understand the process of evolutionary branching (often interpreted as speciation) is central to the related framework of adaptive dynamics (Day, 2005; Geritz et al., 1998).
As with the previous evolutionary frameworks, integrating mechanistic knowledge (including, but not limited to, biomechanics-relevant knowledge) of organisms’ interactions with their environment into this framework would involve extending the fitness function λ. In this case, λ becomes a function of the environment as well as the invader and resident traits. As with quantitative genetics, the theoretical framework for function-valued traits, described for adaptive dynamics by Dieckmann et al. (Dieckmann et al., 2006), provides a possible construct for modeling such traits.
For an illustration of how incorporating mechanistic knowledge of organism–environment interactions might provide different insight from game theoretic models, consider the evolution of dispersal. Models of the evolution of dispersal have a long history in game theory (reviewed by Johnson and Gaines, 1990; Ronce, 2007). The evolving trait in such models typically concerns whether or not dispersal occurs (e.g. proportion of offspring dispersing), with any dispersal occurring in a generic way such as all offspring having an equal likelihood of landing in any site (global dispersal). Recent models have begun to incorporate the evolution of dispersal kernels (functions that describe the probability density of dispersing offspring in space) (e.g. Hovestadt et al., 2001; Rousset and Gandon, 2002) and therefore allow exploration of the evolution of dispersal distance or kernel shape. In contrast, non-evolutionary models of dispersal have a long history of incorporating mechanism, including the influence of the physical environment, to determine the expected shape of the dispersal kernels, especially for wind-dispersed seeds (reviewed by Levin et al., 2003).
A similar development to seed dispersal models, both ecological and evolutionary, has occurred in models of dispersal for marine organisms with both planktonic and benthic stages. Models of the evolution of dispersal for such marine organisms have typically focused on the question of the evolution of feeding (planktotrophic) and non-feeding (lecithotrophic) larvae given life history trade-offs, often based on a fitness optimization approach (where the planktonic stage might serve more as a migration to increase feeding opportunities or decrease predation risk than a dispersal event) (reviewed by Strathmann, 1985). More recent evolutionary models connect the expected offspring size that results from such trade-offs to the average dispersal distance of a dispersal kernel based on phenomenological expectations of the energetic requirements for development to metamorphosis (e.g. Baskett et al., 2007). Most recently, non-evolutionary mechanistic models of the dispersal kernel for marine spores as it depends on currents have recently been built on biomechanics-based knowledge (Gaylord et al., 2006; Gaylord et al., 2012).
The recent extension of evolutionary models to incorporate dispersal kernels and the existence of mechanistic descriptions of dispersal kernels as they connect to the physical environment (the functional response of this example) for wind-dispersed seeds and marine spores provides an opportunity to develop more mechanistic evolutionary models. Incorporating the mechanistic dispersal kernels into evolutionary models would shift the focus of such models from the question of whether or not dispersal (or planktotrophy) evolves to the evolution of a trait that drives dispersal as it depends on the environment. Therefore, such models would allow deeper insight into the evolution of the shape of the dispersal kernel, which is key to a variety of ecological processes from range expansion to community-level diversity (Levin et al., 2003).
Furthermore, even for ecological or evolutionary questions where the exact shape of the dispersal kernel does not have a major impact [e.g. rules of thumb for marine reserve design (Lockwood et al., 2002)], following the evolution of a biomechanics-based dispersal kernel can provide insight into how the expected outcome depends on local or changing environmental conditions [e.g. marine currents (Gaylord et al., 2006)]. The connection between the physical environment and a biologically relevant trait creates the potential to mechanistically consider constraints on dispersal evolution as well. Finally, the focus on biologically relevant traits, in the case of dispersal kernels likely a morphological trait in the dispersal stage, might allow better connection of models to data such as heritability estimates. For example, one crucial gap between theory and data in the context of dispersal evolution is that theoretical predictions and model-based hypotheses about the amount of dispersal are difficult to test against empirical data because dispersal itself is difficult to measure (Ronce, 2007); theoretical predictions about dispersal-related traits under different environmental conditions might provide more opportunities for relevant empirical measurement and tests. This speculative example suggests the general potential for more mechanistic evolutionary models to provide ecological insight, allow greater understanding of evolution under local or changing environmental conditions, and better connect theory and data.
Conservation applications
Both ecological and evolutionary processes occur in the context of human-driven global change (Palumbi, 2001; Vitousek et al., 1997). One proposed strength of a more mechanistic approach to ecological and evolutionary modeling, especially that related to biomechanics, is the enhanced predictive power under novel environmental conditions, such as physiological understanding informing predicted responses to climate change (Denny and Helmuth, 2009; Helmuth et al., 2005; Hoffmann and Sgro, 2011; Hofmann and Todgham, 2010; Kearney et al., 2012; McGill et al., 2006; Norberg, 2004). However, the types of models described here, even with added realism from mechanistic functional responses, remain at the general end of the modeling trade-off described in the Introduction and therefore tend not to have the level of both realism and precision necessary for predictions (Levins, 1966). In addition, the key challenge for ecologists and conservation biologists is not just predicting what will happen under climate change, but informing local science-based management decisions (e.g. reserve design, invasive species control) under a changing climate (Dawson et al., 2011; Heller and Zavaleta, 2009). Vulnerability estimated from predictive models can provide a first step towards conservation management under a changing climate (Rowland et al., 2011), but insight into relative vulnerability and sensitivity to different processes can stem from the more general models described here as well.
One possible component of local management under climate change is to protect the capacity of natural systems to respond to the global changes (Heller and Zavaleta, 2009). On the evolutionary level, protecting response capacity means protecting the potential for genetic adaptation as it depends on properties such as genetic variance, population size and the level of gene flow (Hoffmann and Sgro, 2011; Sgro et al., 2011) where genetic adaptation is one aspect of the population-level response to climate change, along with movement and acclimation (Parmesan, 2006). On the community level, protecting the response capacity involves protecting community-level resistance, resilience and robustness to environmental change as it depends on properties and processes such as diversity, modularity, redundancy and feedback loops (Levin and Lubchenco, 2008). Sensitivity of basic models to different assumptions and parameters can provide insight into which processes and properties are most important to the overall response and therefore inform this aspect of management under climate change.
Sensitivity analysis is an important tool for prioritizing conservation management efforts [e.g. Crouse and colleagues (Crouse et al., 1987) provide a quintessential example of this approach]. For an example related to the question of physiological response to climate change, we constructed a model, rooted in the thermal tolerance fitness function described above, of coral reef ecological and evolutionary response to the future thermal stress expected with climate change (Baskett et al., 2010). Sensitivity analysis of a variety of model constructs and of all model parameters provided an integrative and quantitative comparison of existing recommendations (previously considered qualitatively and occasionally contradictory) for local protection of coral reef resistance, resilience and adaptive capacity in a changing climate.
Generally, incorporating mechanistic functional responses into basic models allows greater connection of model parameters to biologically relevant characteristics (Schoener, 1986), and therefore increases the potential to connect model outcomes to an empirical understanding of important traits or physiological processes. Furthermore, mechanistic functional responses that include interactions with the physical environment will also indicate sensitivity to empirically relevant environmental conditions. Such insights can provide a sense both of which patterns or processes might best allow response capacity and of which local stressors are more likely to interact synergistically with global change, which can suggest prioritization in terms of which locations and processes to protect and which local stressors to protect against. This enhanced realism and biological relevance in the context of basic models could help add much-needed specificity to general recommendations, allowing them to strike the difficult-to-achieve balance between broad applicability and concreteness for recommendations for management under a changing climate (Heller and Zavaleta, 2009).
Conclusions: a trait-based approach
In summary, mechanistic functional responses can readily fit into existing frameworks for modeling species interactions and, in the guise of fitness functions, evolutionary dynamics. Furthermore, mechanistic functional responses that incorporate organisms’ interactions with their environment can extend these frameworks to explore environmental influences, including multispecies or adaptive responses to changing environments and the evolution of phenotypic plasticity. For both community and evolutionary models, this approach ties into existing theoretical frameworks such as trait-mediated interactions (Bolker et al., 2003) and the evolution of function-valued traits (Dieckmann et al., 2006; Kingsolver and Gomulkiewicz, 2003).
These connections highlight how integrating mechanistic functional responses into basic models represents a trait-based approach, where physiological or morphological traits mediate the organism–environment interaction. Therefore, a key model-building decision will be the careful choice of what trait(s) dictate the model system response to the environment (Chevin et al., 2010; Naeem and Wright, 2003; Norberg, 2004). For community models, such traits must be relevant to organism or population performance (McGill et al., 2006; Naeem and Wright, 2003), and for evolutionary models, such traits must have a heritable component as well as be ecologically relevant (Chevin et al., 2010).
Overall, integrating mechanistic functional responses into community and evolutionary models provides a mechanistic underpinning that more readily connects these models to empirical data and environmental conditions [at the cost of some generality (Schoener, 1986)], thus advancing theoretical population biology. In addition, using the aggregated functional responses allows a tractable exploration that draws from existing tools and frameworks in theoretical population biology, thus advancing efforts to integrate biomechanics with ecology in terms of scaling up biomechanics-based knowledge both ecologically and temporally. This can complement more detail-oriented theoretical frameworks that directly model the mechanisms by providing general insight into when mechanism affects population dynamics. The examples discussed here (the classic example of Holling functional responses, recent efforts to incorporate temperature dependence into predator–prey dynamics, the plant resource example of ecosystem engineering, the phenotype–performance–fitness framework, the use of the thermal tolerance envelope as a fitness function in quantitative genetic models, and the potential for integration of mechanistic dispersal kernels in game theoretic frameworks of dispersal evolution) illustrate how mechanistic functional responses can affect quantitative and qualitative dynamics and allow a better connection of theory and data.
Acknowledgements
I am indebted to Mark Denny for the invitation to participate in the 2011 Journal of Experimental Biology Symposium on Integrating Biomechanics and Ecology in addition to valuable feedback on these ideas and previous versions of the manuscript. Insightful conversations with and feedback from Brian Gaylord and Roger Nisbet also contributed to the ideas presented here. Finally, Johan van de Koppel and an anonymous reviewer provided helpful feedback on a previous version of this manuscript.
Footnotes
Funding
This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.